andrew_gelman_stats andrew_gelman_stats-2013 andrew_gelman_stats-2013-2142 knowledge-graph by maker-knowledge-mining

2142 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-21-Chasing the noise


meta infos for this blog

Source: html

Introduction: Fabio Rojas writes : After reading the Fowler/Christakis paper on networks and obesity , a student asked why it was that friends had a stronger influence on spouses. In other words, if we believe the F&C; paper, they report that your friends (57%) are more likely to transmit obesity than your spouse (37%) (see page 370). This might be interpreted in two ways. First, it might be seen as a counter argument. This might really indicate that homophily is at work. We probably select spouses for some traits that are not self-similar. While we choose friends mainly on self-similarity of leisure and consumption (e.g, diet and exercise). Second, there might be an explanation based on transmission. We choose friends because we want them to influence us, while spouses are (supposed?) to accept us. Your thoughts? My thought: No. No no no no no. No no no. No. From the linked paper: A person’s chances of becoming obese increased by 57% (95% confidence interval [CI], 6 to 123) if h


Summary: the most important sentenses genereted by tfidf model

sentIndex sentText sentNum sentScore

1 Fabio Rojas writes : After reading the Fowler/Christakis paper on networks and obesity , a student asked why it was that friends had a stronger influence on spouses. [sent-1, score-0.476]

2 In other words, if we believe the F&C; paper, they report that your friends (57%) are more likely to transmit obesity than your spouse (37%) (see page 370). [sent-2, score-0.46]

3 We probably select spouses for some traits that are not self-similar. [sent-6, score-0.202]

4 We choose friends because we want them to influence us, while spouses are (supposed? [sent-10, score-0.43]

5 From the linked paper: A person’s chances of becoming obese increased by 57% (95% confidence interval [CI], 6 to 123) if he or she had a friend who became obese in a given interval. [sent-17, score-0.74]

6 If one spouse became obese, the likelihood that the other spouse would become obese increased by 37% (95% CI, 7 to 73). [sent-21, score-0.633]

7 The mistake made by Rojas’s student is to overinterpret chance variation. [sent-28, score-0.304]

8 Amy sinks 6 out of 20 shots, and Beth sinks 4 out of 20. [sent-32, score-0.254]

9 The difference could easily, easily be explained by chance. [sent-41, score-0.176]

10 It’s not that any of these (hypothetical) explanations are necessarily wrong —indeed, they could all be true, it could be that Amy’s family is more supportive and that Beth was under more pressure etc etc—but there’s essentially no evidence to support them. [sent-42, score-0.722]

11 The explanations could just have well been made before any shots were even taken. [sent-43, score-0.465]

12 The trouble is that they’re being used to explain a pattern that could well be noise. [sent-47, score-0.248]

13 It still could be a useful exercise: first explain pattern A, then explain pattern not-A. [sent-48, score-0.42]

14 Even if you completely accept the framework of the published research and don’t worry about any selection effects, you’re comparing the confidence interval [6, 123] to the interval [7, 73]. [sent-51, score-0.337]

15 This is just a good opportunity to bring up an issue that occurs a lot in social science: lots of theorizing to explain natural fluctuations that occur in a random sample. [sent-56, score-0.191]

16 ) The point here is not that some anonymous student made a mistake but rather that this is a mistake that gets made by researchers, journalists, and the general public all the time. [sent-58, score-0.443]

17 Just remember that if, as is here, the data are equivocal, that it would be just as valuable to give explanations that go in the opposite direction. [sent-60, score-0.231]

18 The data here are completely consistent with the alternative hypothesis that people follow their spouses more than their friends when it comes to obesity. [sent-61, score-0.374]

19 I checked back on Rojas’s post and, scarily enough, two of the three comments offer potential explanations for the difference, with neither commenter seeming to realize that they are chasing noise. [sent-64, score-0.435]

20 Again, there’s nothing wrong with theorizing but I think it’s helpful to realize that these are pure speculations with essentially no basis in data, so one could just as well be giving explanations for why the underlying difference goes in the opposite direction. [sent-65, score-0.744]


similar blogs computed by tfidf model

tfidf for this blog:

wordName wordTfidf (topN-words)

[('beth', 0.406), ('amy', 0.382), ('rojas', 0.26), ('obese', 0.219), ('spouses', 0.202), ('explanations', 0.173), ('friends', 0.172), ('student', 0.165), ('shots', 0.157), ('spouse', 0.147), ('sinks', 0.127), ('difference', 0.1), ('interval', 0.099), ('theorizing', 0.098), ('explain', 0.093), ('chasing', 0.091), ('christakis', 0.088), ('ci', 0.088), ('fowler', 0.084), ('supportive', 0.084), ('confidence', 0.083), ('obesity', 0.083), ('success', 0.082), ('mistake', 0.08), ('basketball', 0.079), ('pattern', 0.079), ('essentially', 0.076), ('could', 0.076), ('pressure', 0.071), ('exercise', 0.069), ('significant', 0.066), ('theories', 0.062), ('intervals', 0.062), ('became', 0.06), ('increased', 0.06), ('made', 0.059), ('neither', 0.059), ('seeming', 0.058), ('transmit', 0.058), ('opposite', 0.058), ('family', 0.057), ('accept', 0.056), ('influence', 0.056), ('evidence', 0.055), ('nothing', 0.055), ('cm', 0.055), ('homophily', 0.055), ('realize', 0.054), ('estimate', 0.054), ('wrong', 0.054)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

same-blog 1 1.0 2142 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-21-Chasing the noise

Introduction: Fabio Rojas writes : After reading the Fowler/Christakis paper on networks and obesity , a student asked why it was that friends had a stronger influence on spouses. In other words, if we believe the F&C; paper, they report that your friends (57%) are more likely to transmit obesity than your spouse (37%) (see page 370). This might be interpreted in two ways. First, it might be seen as a counter argument. This might really indicate that homophily is at work. We probably select spouses for some traits that are not self-similar. While we choose friends mainly on self-similarity of leisure and consumption (e.g, diet and exercise). Second, there might be an explanation based on transmission. We choose friends because we want them to influence us, while spouses are (supposed?) to accept us. Your thoughts? My thought: No. No no no no no. No no no. No. From the linked paper: A person’s chances of becoming obese increased by 57% (95% confidence interval [CI], 6 to 123) if h

2 0.22343026 1282 andrew gelman stats-2012-04-26-Bad news about (some) statisticians

Introduction: Sociologist Fabio Rojas reports on “a conversation I [Rojas] have had a few times with statisticians”: Rojas: “What does your research tell us about a sample of, say, a few hundred cases?” Statistician: “That’s not important. My result works as n–> 00.” Rojas: “Sure, that’s a fine mathematical result, but I have to estimate the model with, like, totally finite data. I need inference, not limits. Maybe the estimate doesn’t work out so well for small n.” Statistician: “Sure, but if you have a few million cases, it’ll work in the limit.” Rojas: “Whoa. Have you ever collected, like, real world network data? A million cases is hard to get.” The conversation continues in this frustrating vein. Rojas writes: This illustrates a fundamental issue in statistics (and other sciences). One you formalize a model and work mathematically, you are tempted to focus on what is mathematically interesting instead of the underlying problem motivating the science. . . . We have the sam

3 0.17020857 1742 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-27-What is “explanation”?

Introduction: “Explanation” is this thing that social scientists (or people in their everyday lives, acting like social scientists) do, where some event X happens and we supply a coherent story that concludes with X. Sometimes we speak of an event as “overdetermined,” when we can think of many plausible stories that all lead to X. My question today is: what is explanation, in a statistical sense? To understand why this is a question worth asking at all, compare to prediction. Prediction is another thing that we all to, typically in a qualitative fashion: I think she’s gonna win this struggle, I think he’s probably gonna look for a new job, etc. It’s pretty clear how to map everyday prediction into a statistical framework, and we can think of informal qualitative predictions as approximations to the predictions that could be made by a statistical model (as in the classic work of Meehl and others on clinical vs. statistical prediction). Fitting “explanation” into a statistical framework i

4 0.14208391 757 andrew gelman stats-2011-06-10-Controversy over the Christakis-Fowler findings on the contagion of obesity

Introduction: Nicholas Christakis and James Fowler are famous for finding that obesity is contagious. Their claims, which have been received with both respect and skepticism (perhaps we need a new word for this: “respecticism”?) are based on analysis of data from the Framingham heart study, a large longitudinal public-health study that happened to have some social network data (for the odd reason that each participant was asked to provide the name of a friend who could help the researchers locate them if they were to move away during the study period. The short story is that if your close contact became obese, you were likely to become obese also. The long story is a debate about the reliability of this finding (that is, can it be explained by measurement error and sampling variability) and its causal implications. This sort of study is in my wheelhouse, as it were, but I have never looked at the Christakis-Fowler work in detail. Thus, my previous and current comments are more along the line

5 0.12905762 480 andrew gelman stats-2010-12-21-Instead of “confidence interval,” let’s say “uncertainty interval”

Introduction: I’ve become increasingly uncomfortable with the term “confidence interval,” for several reasons: - The well-known difficulties in interpretation (officially the confidence statement can be interpreted only on average, but people typically implicitly give the Bayesian interpretation to each case), - The ambiguity between confidence intervals and predictive intervals. (See the footnote in BDA where we discuss the difference between “inference” and “prediction” in the classical framework.) - The awkwardness of explaining that confidence intervals are big in noisy situations where you have less confidence, and confidence intervals are small when you have more confidence. So here’s my proposal. Let’s use the term “uncertainty interval” instead. The uncertainty interval tells you how much uncertainty you have. That works pretty well, I think. P.S. As of this writing, “confidence interval” outGoogles “uncertainty interval” by the huge margin of 9.5 million to 54000. So we

6 0.12877607 1672 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-14-How do you think about the values in a confidence interval?

7 0.12450378 2042 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-28-Difficulties of using statistical significance (or lack thereof) to sift through and compare research hypotheses

8 0.1184058 1913 andrew gelman stats-2013-06-24-Why it doesn’t make sense in general to form confidence intervals by inverting hypothesis tests

9 0.11694957 870 andrew gelman stats-2011-08-25-Why it doesn’t make sense in general to form confidence intervals by inverting hypothesis tests

10 0.11165128 462 andrew gelman stats-2010-12-10-Who’s holding the pen?, The split screen, and other ideas for one-on-one instruction

11 0.1078963 2287 andrew gelman stats-2014-04-09-Advice: positive-sum, zero-sum, or negative-sum

12 0.097842157 1844 andrew gelman stats-2013-05-06-Against optimism about social science

13 0.094461225 1564 andrew gelman stats-2012-11-06-Choose your default, or your default will choose you (election forecasting edition)

14 0.089098468 756 andrew gelman stats-2011-06-10-Christakis-Fowler update

15 0.088885233 399 andrew gelman stats-2010-11-07-Challenges of experimental design; also another rant on the practice of mentioning the publication of an article but not naming its author

16 0.087244414 2156 andrew gelman stats-2014-01-01-“Though They May Be Unaware, Newlyweds Implicitly Know Whether Their Marriage Will Be Satisfying”

17 0.087121539 1952 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-23-Christakis response to my comment on his comments on social science (or just skip to the P.P.P.S. at the end)

18 0.086838834 899 andrew gelman stats-2011-09-10-The statistical significance filter

19 0.085154615 1072 andrew gelman stats-2011-12-19-“The difference between . . .”: It’s not just p=.05 vs. p=.06

20 0.084848464 1699 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-31-Fowlerpalooza!


similar blogs computed by lsi model

lsi for this blog:

topicId topicWeight

[(0, 0.189), (1, -0.022), (2, 0.022), (3, -0.077), (4, -0.006), (5, -0.019), (6, 0.02), (7, 0.043), (8, 0.003), (9, -0.056), (10, -0.026), (11, 0.025), (12, -0.01), (13, -0.054), (14, -0.03), (15, -0.009), (16, 0.003), (17, -0.014), (18, 0.004), (19, -0.036), (20, 0.031), (21, 0.013), (22, 0.017), (23, -0.004), (24, 0.048), (25, -0.039), (26, 0.029), (27, -0.038), (28, -0.041), (29, 0.007), (30, -0.027), (31, -0.011), (32, -0.041), (33, -0.047), (34, 0.037), (35, 0.033), (36, -0.026), (37, 0.028), (38, -0.009), (39, -0.019), (40, 0.011), (41, -0.023), (42, 0.016), (43, -0.004), (44, 0.005), (45, 0.003), (46, 0.001), (47, -0.025), (48, -0.025), (49, -0.017)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

same-blog 1 0.94421536 2142 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-21-Chasing the noise

Introduction: Fabio Rojas writes : After reading the Fowler/Christakis paper on networks and obesity , a student asked why it was that friends had a stronger influence on spouses. In other words, if we believe the F&C; paper, they report that your friends (57%) are more likely to transmit obesity than your spouse (37%) (see page 370). This might be interpreted in two ways. First, it might be seen as a counter argument. This might really indicate that homophily is at work. We probably select spouses for some traits that are not self-similar. While we choose friends mainly on self-similarity of leisure and consumption (e.g, diet and exercise). Second, there might be an explanation based on transmission. We choose friends because we want them to influence us, while spouses are (supposed?) to accept us. Your thoughts? My thought: No. No no no no no. No no no. No. From the linked paper: A person’s chances of becoming obese increased by 57% (95% confidence interval [CI], 6 to 123) if h

2 0.78849763 2248 andrew gelman stats-2014-03-15-Problematic interpretations of confidence intervals

Introduction: Rink Hoekstra writes: A couple of months ago, you were visiting the University of Groningen, and after the talk you gave there I spoke briefly with you about a study that I conducted with Richard Morey, Jeff Rouder and Eric-Jan Wagenmakers. In the study, we found that researchers’  knowledge of how to interpret a confidence interval (CI), was almost as limited as the knowledge of students who had had no inferential statistics course yet. Our manuscript was recently accepted for publication in  Psychonomic Bulletin & Review , and it’s now available online (see e.g.,  here ). Maybe it’s interesting to discuss on your blog, especially since CIs are often promoted (for example in the new guidelines of Psychological Science ), but apparently researchers seem to have little idea how to interpret them. Given that the confidence percentage of a CI tells something about the procedure rather than about the data at hand, this might be understandable, but, according to us, it’s problematic neve

3 0.7819066 1672 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-14-How do you think about the values in a confidence interval?

Introduction: Philip Jones writes: As an interested reader of your blog, I wondered if you might consider a blog entry sometime on the following question I posed on CrossValidated (StackExchange). I originally posed the question based on my uncertainty about 95% CIs: “Are all values within the 95% CI equally likely (probable), or are the values at the “tails” of the 95% CI less likely than those in the middle of the CI closer to the point estimate?” I posed this question based on discordant information I found at a couple of different web sources (I posted these sources in the body of the question). I received some interesting replies, and the replies were not unanimous, in fact there is some serious disagreement there! After seeing this disagreement, I naturally thought of you, and whether you might be able to clear this up. Please note I am not referring to credible intervals, but rather to the common medical journal reporting standard of confidence intervals. My response: First

4 0.77926379 2042 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-28-Difficulties of using statistical significance (or lack thereof) to sift through and compare research hypotheses

Introduction: Dean Eckles writes: Thought you might be interested in an example that touches on a couple recurring topics: 1. The difference between a statistically significant finding and one that is non-significant need not be itself statistically significant (thus highlighting the problems of using NHST to declare whether an effect exists or not). 2. Continued issues with the credibility of high profile studies of “social contagion”, especially by Christakis and Fowler . A new paper in Archives of Sexual Behavior produces observational estimates of peer effects in sexual behavior and same-sex attraction. In the text, the authors (who include C&F;) make repeated comparisons of the results for peer effects in sexual intercourse and those for peer effects in same-sex attraction. However, the 95% CI for the later actually includes the point estimate for the former! This is most clear in Figure 2, as highlighted by Real Clear Science’s blog post about the study. (Now because there is som

5 0.72002971 2223 andrew gelman stats-2014-02-24-“Edlin’s rule” for routinely scaling down published estimates

Introduction: A few months ago I reacted (see further discussion in comments here ) to a recent study on early childhood intervention, in which researchers Paul Gertler, James Heckman, Rodrigo Pinto, Arianna Zanolini, Christel Vermeerch, Susan Walker, Susan M. Chang, and Sally Grantham-McGregor estimated that a particular intervention on young children had raised incomes on young adults by 42%. I wrote: Major decisions on education policy can turn on the statistical interpretation of small, idiosyncratic data sets — in this case, a study of 129 Jamaican children. . . . Overall, I have no reason to doubt the direction of the effect, namely, that psychosocial stimulation should be good. But I’m skeptical of the claim that income differed by 42%, due to the reason of the statistical significance filter . In section 2.3, the authors are doing lots of hypothesizing based on some comparisons being statistically significant and others being non-significant. There’s nothing wrong with speculation, b

6 0.71968436 706 andrew gelman stats-2011-05-11-The happiness gene: My bottom line (for now)

7 0.71358389 1968 andrew gelman stats-2013-08-05-Evidence on the impact of sustained use of polynomial regression on causal inference (a claim that coal heating is reducing lifespan by 5 years for half a billion people)

8 0.71163911 2241 andrew gelman stats-2014-03-10-Preregistration: what’s in it for you?

9 0.70656854 1662 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-09-The difference between “significant” and “non-significant” is not itself statistically significant

10 0.70175529 2227 andrew gelman stats-2014-02-27-“What Can we Learn from the Many Labs Replication Project?”

11 0.70062643 775 andrew gelman stats-2011-06-21-Fundamental difficulty of inference for a ratio when the denominator could be positive or negative

12 0.70043063 2156 andrew gelman stats-2014-01-01-“Though They May Be Unaware, Newlyweds Implicitly Know Whether Their Marriage Will Be Satisfying”

13 0.69565934 1876 andrew gelman stats-2013-05-29-Another one of those “Psychological Science” papers (this time on biceps size and political attitudes among college students)

14 0.6947335 1702 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-01-Don’t let your standard errors drive your research agenda

15 0.69416243 2355 andrew gelman stats-2014-05-31-Jessica Tracy and Alec Beall (authors of the fertile-women-wear-pink study) comment on our Garden of Forking Paths paper, and I comment on their comments

16 0.68963784 1114 andrew gelman stats-2012-01-12-Controversy about average personality differences between men and women

17 0.68840349 957 andrew gelman stats-2011-10-14-Questions about a study of charter schools

18 0.68394876 1838 andrew gelman stats-2013-05-03-Setting aside the politics, the debate over the new health-care study reveals that we’re moving to a new high standard of statistical journalism

19 0.68199468 351 andrew gelman stats-2010-10-18-“I was finding the test so irritating and boring that I just started to click through as fast as I could”

20 0.6793316 212 andrew gelman stats-2010-08-17-Futures contracts, Granger causality, and my preference for estimation to testing


similar blogs computed by lda model

lda for this blog:

topicId topicWeight

[(0, 0.022), (7, 0.012), (12, 0.029), (16, 0.066), (17, 0.025), (18, 0.015), (21, 0.109), (24, 0.14), (63, 0.015), (65, 0.044), (67, 0.02), (70, 0.013), (79, 0.047), (89, 0.058), (99, 0.29)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

same-blog 1 0.96014971 2142 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-21-Chasing the noise

Introduction: Fabio Rojas writes : After reading the Fowler/Christakis paper on networks and obesity , a student asked why it was that friends had a stronger influence on spouses. In other words, if we believe the F&C; paper, they report that your friends (57%) are more likely to transmit obesity than your spouse (37%) (see page 370). This might be interpreted in two ways. First, it might be seen as a counter argument. This might really indicate that homophily is at work. We probably select spouses for some traits that are not self-similar. While we choose friends mainly on self-similarity of leisure and consumption (e.g, diet and exercise). Second, there might be an explanation based on transmission. We choose friends because we want them to influence us, while spouses are (supposed?) to accept us. Your thoughts? My thought: No. No no no no no. No no no. No. From the linked paper: A person’s chances of becoming obese increased by 57% (95% confidence interval [CI], 6 to 123) if h

2 0.95371586 147 andrew gelman stats-2010-07-15-Quote of the day: statisticians and defaults

Introduction: On statisticians and statistical software: Statisticians are particularly sensitive to default settings, which makes sense considering that statistics is, in many ways, a science based on defaults. What is a “statistical method” if not a recommended default analysis, backed up by some combination of theory and experience?

3 0.95285159 659 andrew gelman stats-2011-04-13-Jim Campbell argues that Larry Bartels’s “Unequal Democracy” findings are not robust

Introduction: A few years ago Larry Bartels presented this graph, a version of which latter appeared in his book Unequal Democracy: Larry looked at the data in a number of ways, and the evidence seemed convincing that, at least in the short term, the Democrats were better than Republicans for the economy. This is consistent with Democrats’ general policies of lowering unemployment, as compared to Republicans lowering inflation, and, by comparing first-term to second-term presidents, he found that the result couldn’t simply be explained as a rebound or alternation pattern. The question then arose, why have the Republicans won so many elections? Why aren’t the Democrats consistently dominating? Non-economic issues are part of the story, of course, but lots of evidence shows the economy to be a key concern for voters, so it’s still hard to see how, with a pattern such as shown above, the Republicans could keep winning. Larry had some explanations, largely having to do with timing: under De

4 0.95266503 2037 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-25-Classical probability does not apply to quantum systems (causal inference edition)

Introduction: James Robins, Tyler VanderWeele, and Richard Gill write : Neyman introduced a formal mathematical theory of counterfactual causation that now has become standard language in many quantitative disciplines, but not in physics. We use results on causal interaction and interference between treatments (derived under the Neyman theory) to give a simple new proof of a well-known result in quantum physics, namely, Bellís inequality. Now the predictions of quantum mechanics and the results of experiment both violate Bell’s inequality. In the remainder of the talk, we review the implications for a counterfactual theory of causation. Assuming with Einstein that faster than light (supraluminal) communication is not possible, one can view the Neyman theory of counterfactuals as falsified by experiment. . . . Is it safe for a quantitative discipline to rely on a counterfactual approach to causation, when our best confirmed physical theory falsifies their existence? I haven’t seen the talk

5 0.95256692 514 andrew gelman stats-2011-01-13-News coverage of statistical issues…how did I do?

Introduction: This post is by Phil Price. A reporter once told me that the worst-kept secret of journalism is that every story has errors. And it’s true that just about every time I know about something first-hand, the news stories about it have some mistakes. Reporters aren’t subject-matter experts, they have limited time, and they generally can’t keep revisiting the things they are saying and checking them for accuracy. Many of us have published papers with errors — my most recent paper has an incorrect figure — and that’s after working on them carefully for weeks! One way that reporters can try to get things right is by quoting experts. Even then, there are problems with taking quotes out of context, or with making poor choices about what material to include or exclude, or, of course, with making a poor selection of experts. Yesterday, I was interviewed by an NPR reporter about the risks of breathing radon (a naturally occurring radioactive gas): who should test for it, how dangerous

6 0.9516663 1824 andrew gelman stats-2013-04-25-Fascinating graphs from facebook data

7 0.95130754 789 andrew gelman stats-2011-07-07-Descriptive statistics, causal inference, and story time

8 0.95100224 1728 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-19-The grasshopper wins, and Greg Mankiw’s grandmother would be “shocked and appalled” all over again

9 0.95007205 1675 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-15-“10 Things You Need to Know About Causal Effects”

10 0.94960898 810 andrew gelman stats-2011-07-20-Adding more information can make the variance go up (depending on your model)

11 0.94862521 1989 andrew gelman stats-2013-08-20-Correcting for multiple comparisons in a Bayesian regression model

12 0.94844413 2306 andrew gelman stats-2014-04-26-Sleazy sock puppet can’t stop spamming our discussion of compressed sensing and promoting the work of Xiteng Liu

13 0.94460666 486 andrew gelman stats-2010-12-26-Age and happiness: The pattern isn’t as clear as you might think

14 0.9414078 1702 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-01-Don’t let your standard errors drive your research agenda

15 0.94061184 2281 andrew gelman stats-2014-04-04-The Notorious N.H.S.T. presents: Mo P-values Mo Problems

16 0.93997526 432 andrew gelman stats-2010-11-27-Neumann update

17 0.93975896 1459 andrew gelman stats-2012-08-15-How I think about mixture models

18 0.9391591 1275 andrew gelman stats-2012-04-22-Please stop me before I barf again

19 0.93871009 2112 andrew gelman stats-2013-11-25-An interesting but flawed attempt to apply general forecasting principles to contextualize attitudes toward risks of global warming

20 0.93724203 2159 andrew gelman stats-2014-01-04-“Dogs are sensitive to small variations of the Earth’s magnetic field”