andrew_gelman_stats andrew_gelman_stats-2013 andrew_gelman_stats-2013-1695 knowledge-graph by maker-knowledge-mining

1695 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-28-Economists argue about Bayes


meta infos for this blog

Source: html

Introduction: Robert Bell pointed me to this post by Brad De Long on Bayesian statistics, and then I also noticed this from Noah Smith, who wrote: My impression is that although the Bayesian/Frequentist debate is interesting and intellectually fun, there’s really not much “there” there… despite being so-hip-right-now, Bayesian is not the Statistical Jesus. I’m happy to see the discussion going in this direction. Twenty-five years ago or so, when I got into this biz, there were some serious anti-Bayesian attitudes floating around in mainstream statistics. Discussions in the journals sometimes devolved into debates of the form, “Bayesians: knaves or fools?”. You’d get all sorts of free-floating skepticism about any prior distribution at all, even while people were accepting without question (and doing theory on) logistic regressions, proportional hazards models, and all sorts of strong strong models. (In the subfield of survey sampling, various prominent researchers would refuse to mode


Summary: the most important sentenses genereted by tfidf model

sentIndex sentText sentNum sentScore

1 You’d get all sorts of free-floating skepticism about any prior distribution at all, even while people were accepting without question (and doing theory on) logistic regressions, proportional hazards models, and all sorts of strong strong models. [sent-6, score-0.599]

2 (In the subfield of survey sampling, various prominent researchers would refuse to model the data at all while having no problem treating nominal sampling problems as if they were real (despite this sort of evidence to the contrary). [sent-7, score-0.357]

3 Those were the dark days, when even to do Bayesian inference (outside of some small set of fenced-in topics such as genetics that had very clear prior distributions) made you suspect in some quarters. [sent-9, score-0.386]

4 Bayesian methods are not only accepted, they’re thriving to the extent that in many cases the strongest argument against Bayes is that it’s not universally wonderful (a point with which I agree; see yesterday’s discussion ). [sent-12, score-0.373]

5 The field really has moved forward, and indeed one reason why I don’t think Bayesian methods are always so necessary is that non-Bayesian methods use similar ideas. [sent-21, score-0.35]

6 Take-home message for economists One thing I’d like economists to get out of this discussion is: statistical ideas matter. [sent-23, score-0.289]

7 A lot of the best statistical methods out there—however labeled—work by combining lots of information and modeling the resulting variation. [sent-31, score-0.389]

8 Instead, hypothesis testing typically means that you do what’s necessary to get statistical significance, then you make a very strong claim that might make no sense at all. [sent-37, score-0.621]

9 Or, conversely, you slice the data up into little pieces so that no single piece is statistically significant, and then act as if the effect you’re studying is zero. [sent-39, score-0.325]

10 The sad story of conventional hypothesis testing is that it is all to quick to run with a statistically significant result even if it’s coming from noise. [sent-40, score-0.368]

11 Smith elaborates and makes another mistake, writing: If I have a strong prior, and crappy data, in Bayesian I know exactly what to do; I stick with my priors. [sent-42, score-0.344]

12 In Frequentist, nobody tells me what to do, but what I’ll probably do is weaken my prior based on the fact that I couldn’t find strong support for it. [sent-43, score-0.452]

13 Third, if you have weak data and your prior is informative, this does not imply that your prior should be weakened! [sent-51, score-0.828]

14 If my prior reading of the literature suggests that a parameter theta should be between -0. [sent-52, score-0.383]

15 I very much respect the idea of data reduction and summarizing the information from any particular study without prejudice, but if I have to make a decision or a scientific inference, then I see no reason to rely on whatever small dataset happens to be in my viewer right now. [sent-55, score-0.636]

16 No matter how kosher the data summary was (and, actually, in that case the published analysis had problems even as a classical data summary), the punchline of the paper was a generalization about the population—an inference. [sent-60, score-0.485]

17 Still, there’s a lot more information in the mass of polls than in any single survey. [sent-64, score-0.305]

18 So, to the extent that “Bayesian” is associated with using additional information rather than relying on a single dataset, I see why Nate is happy to associate himself with that label. [sent-65, score-0.299]

19 To put it another way: to the non-Bayesian, a Bayesian is someone who pollutes clean data with a subjective prior distribution. [sent-66, score-0.593]

20 Again, I see that this can be a useful principle for creating data summaries (each polling organization can report its own numbers based on its own data) but it doesn’t make a lot of sense to me if the goal is decision making or scientific inference. [sent-68, score-0.612]


similar blogs computed by tfidf model

tfidf for this blog:

wordName wordTfidf (topN-words)

[('prior', 0.305), ('bayesian', 0.216), ('smith', 0.202), ('data', 0.148), ('strong', 0.147), ('bayesians', 0.144), ('information', 0.135), ('dataset', 0.133), ('regularization', 0.128), ('stick', 0.121), ('classical', 0.119), ('statistically', 0.106), ('indeed', 0.104), ('lot', 0.099), ('significant', 0.097), ('see', 0.093), ('methods', 0.093), ('informative', 0.088), ('testing', 0.087), ('bayes', 0.085), ('paradigm', 0.084), ('summaries', 0.084), ('economists', 0.082), ('inference', 0.081), ('nate', 0.081), ('theta', 0.078), ('hypothesis', 0.078), ('another', 0.076), ('de', 0.076), ('prominent', 0.076), ('frequentist', 0.072), ('single', 0.071), ('problems', 0.07), ('weak', 0.07), ('progress', 0.067), ('despite', 0.064), ('scientific', 0.064), ('pollutes', 0.064), ('thriving', 0.064), ('example', 0.064), ('model', 0.063), ('make', 0.063), ('discussion', 0.063), ('statements', 0.062), ('statistical', 0.062), ('sense', 0.061), ('astray', 0.06), ('universally', 0.06), ('knaves', 0.06), ('necessary', 0.06)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

same-blog 1 1.0 1695 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-28-Economists argue about Bayes

Introduction: Robert Bell pointed me to this post by Brad De Long on Bayesian statistics, and then I also noticed this from Noah Smith, who wrote: My impression is that although the Bayesian/Frequentist debate is interesting and intellectually fun, there’s really not much “there” there… despite being so-hip-right-now, Bayesian is not the Statistical Jesus. I’m happy to see the discussion going in this direction. Twenty-five years ago or so, when I got into this biz, there were some serious anti-Bayesian attitudes floating around in mainstream statistics. Discussions in the journals sometimes devolved into debates of the form, “Bayesians: knaves or fools?”. You’d get all sorts of free-floating skepticism about any prior distribution at all, even while people were accepting without question (and doing theory on) logistic regressions, proportional hazards models, and all sorts of strong strong models. (In the subfield of survey sampling, various prominent researchers would refuse to mode

2 0.36102095 2109 andrew gelman stats-2013-11-21-Hidden dangers of noninformative priors

Introduction: Following up on Christian’s post [link fixed] on the topic, I’d like to offer a few thoughts of my own. In BDA, we express the idea that a noninformative prior is a placeholder: you can use the noninformative prior to get the analysis started, then if your posterior distribution is less informative than you would like, or if it does not make sense, you can go back and add prior information. Same thing for the data model (the “likelihood”), for that matter: it often makes sense to start with something simple and conventional and then go from there. So, in that sense, noninformative priors are no big deal, they’re just a way to get started. Just don’t take them too seriously. Traditionally in statistics we’ve worked with the paradigm of a single highly informative dataset with only weak external information. But if the data are sparse and prior information is strong, we have to think differently. And, when you increase the dimensionality of a problem, both these things hap

3 0.34822267 1941 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-16-Priors

Introduction: Nick Firoozye writes: While I am absolutely sympathetic to the Bayesian agenda I am often troubled by the requirement of having priors. We must have priors on the parameter of an infinite number of model we have never seen before and I find this troubling. There is a similarly troubling problem in economics of utility theory. Utility is on consumables. To be complete a consumer must assign utility to all sorts of things they never would have encountered. More recent versions of utility theory instead make consumption goods a portfolio of attributes. Cadillacs are x many units of luxury y of transport etc etc. And we can automatically have personal utilities to all these attributes. I don’t ever see parameters. Some model have few and some have hundreds. Instead, I see data. So I don’t know how to have an opinion on parameters themselves. Rather I think it far more natural to have opinions on the behavior of models. The prior predictive density is a good and sensible notion. Also

4 0.3141143 1149 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-01-Philosophy of Bayesian statistics: my reactions to Cox and Mayo

Introduction: The journal Rationality, Markets and Morals has finally posted all the articles in their special issue on the philosophy of Bayesian statistics. My contribution is called Induction and Deduction in Bayesian Data Analysis. I’ll also post my reactions to the other articles. I wrote these notes a few weeks ago and could post them all at once, but I think it will be easier if I post my reactions to each article separately. To start with my best material, here’s my reaction to David Cox and Deborah Mayo, “A Statistical Scientist Meets a Philosopher of Science.” I recommend you read all the way through my long note below; there’s good stuff throughout: 1. Cox: “[Philosophy] forces us to say what it is that we really want to know when we analyze a situation statistically.” This reminds me of a standard question that Don Rubin (who, unlike me, has little use for philosophy in his research) asks in virtually any situation: “What would you do if you had all the data?” For

5 0.28557462 1155 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-05-What is a prior distribution?

Introduction: Some recent blog discussion revealed some confusion that I’ll try to resolve here. I wrote that I’m not a big fan of subjective priors. Various commenters had difficulty with this point, and I think the issue was most clearly stated by Bill Jeff re erys, who wrote : It seems to me that your prior has to reflect your subjective information before you look at the data. How can it not? But this does not mean that the (subjective) prior that you choose is irrefutable; Surely a prior that reflects prior information just does not have to be inconsistent with that information. But that still leaves a range of priors that are consistent with it, the sort of priors that one would use in a sensitivity analysis, for example. I think I see what Bill is getting at. A prior represents your subjective belief, or some approximation to your subjective belief, even if it’s not perfect. That sounds reasonable but I don’t think it works. Or, at least, it often doesn’t work. Let’s start

6 0.27965978 1092 andrew gelman stats-2011-12-29-More by Berger and me on weakly informative priors

7 0.27709764 1779 andrew gelman stats-2013-03-27-“Two Dogmas of Strong Objective Bayesianism”

8 0.25743663 1469 andrew gelman stats-2012-08-25-Ways of knowing

9 0.24511315 781 andrew gelman stats-2011-06-28-The holes in my philosophy of Bayesian data analysis

10 0.23975806 2200 andrew gelman stats-2014-02-05-Prior distribution for a predicted probability

11 0.23704493 1087 andrew gelman stats-2011-12-27-“Keeping things unridiculous”: Berger, O’Hagan, and me on weakly informative priors

12 0.23675339 1247 andrew gelman stats-2012-04-05-More philosophy of Bayes

13 0.23430426 1474 andrew gelman stats-2012-08-29-More on scaled-inverse Wishart and prior independence

14 0.22611372 291 andrew gelman stats-2010-09-22-Philosophy of Bayes and non-Bayes: A dialogue with Deborah Mayo

15 0.22503917 1946 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-19-Prior distributions on derived quantities rather than on parameters themselves

16 0.22013801 1182 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-24-Untangling the Jeffreys-Lindley paradox

17 0.21912411 1719 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-11-Why waste time philosophizing?

18 0.21439707 244 andrew gelman stats-2010-08-30-Useful models, model checking, and external validation: a mini-discussion

19 0.2143576 2017 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-11-“Informative g-Priors for Logistic Regression”

20 0.21028158 1769 andrew gelman stats-2013-03-18-Tibshirani announces new research result: A significance test for the lasso


similar blogs computed by lsi model

lsi for this blog:

topicId topicWeight

[(0, 0.437), (1, 0.245), (2, -0.072), (3, 0.029), (4, -0.17), (5, -0.11), (6, 0.027), (7, 0.103), (8, -0.105), (9, -0.022), (10, -0.018), (11, -0.048), (12, 0.073), (13, 0.012), (14, 0.03), (15, 0.011), (16, -0.023), (17, 0.002), (18, 0.037), (19, 0.008), (20, -0.028), (21, 0.019), (22, -0.055), (23, 0.036), (24, -0.054), (25, -0.0), (26, 0.051), (27, -0.063), (28, -0.016), (29, 0.034), (30, 0.046), (31, -0.001), (32, 0.031), (33, -0.038), (34, 0.027), (35, 0.084), (36, -0.02), (37, 0.017), (38, -0.039), (39, 0.033), (40, -0.013), (41, 0.081), (42, -0.01), (43, -0.025), (44, -0.026), (45, -0.01), (46, 0.015), (47, -0.069), (48, 0.005), (49, 0.006)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

same-blog 1 0.97896385 1695 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-28-Economists argue about Bayes

Introduction: Robert Bell pointed me to this post by Brad De Long on Bayesian statistics, and then I also noticed this from Noah Smith, who wrote: My impression is that although the Bayesian/Frequentist debate is interesting and intellectually fun, there’s really not much “there” there… despite being so-hip-right-now, Bayesian is not the Statistical Jesus. I’m happy to see the discussion going in this direction. Twenty-five years ago or so, when I got into this biz, there were some serious anti-Bayesian attitudes floating around in mainstream statistics. Discussions in the journals sometimes devolved into debates of the form, “Bayesians: knaves or fools?”. You’d get all sorts of free-floating skepticism about any prior distribution at all, even while people were accepting without question (and doing theory on) logistic regressions, proportional hazards models, and all sorts of strong strong models. (In the subfield of survey sampling, various prominent researchers would refuse to mode

2 0.92867053 1149 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-01-Philosophy of Bayesian statistics: my reactions to Cox and Mayo

Introduction: The journal Rationality, Markets and Morals has finally posted all the articles in their special issue on the philosophy of Bayesian statistics. My contribution is called Induction and Deduction in Bayesian Data Analysis. I’ll also post my reactions to the other articles. I wrote these notes a few weeks ago and could post them all at once, but I think it will be easier if I post my reactions to each article separately. To start with my best material, here’s my reaction to David Cox and Deborah Mayo, “A Statistical Scientist Meets a Philosopher of Science.” I recommend you read all the way through my long note below; there’s good stuff throughout: 1. Cox: “[Philosophy] forces us to say what it is that we really want to know when we analyze a situation statistically.” This reminds me of a standard question that Don Rubin (who, unlike me, has little use for philosophy in his research) asks in virtually any situation: “What would you do if you had all the data?” For

3 0.90524995 1157 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-07-Philosophy of Bayesian statistics: my reactions to Hendry

Introduction: Continuing with my discussion here and here of the articles in the special issue of the journal Rationality, Markets and Morals on the philosophy of Bayesian statistics: David Hendry, “Empirical Economic Model Discovery and Theory Evaluation”: Hendry presents a wide-ranging overview of scientific learning, with an interesting comparison of physical with social sciences. (For some reason, he discusses many physical sciences but restricts his social-science examples to economics and psychology.) The only part of Hendry’s long and interesting article that I will discuss, however, is the part where he decides to take a gratuitous swing at Bayes. I don’t know why he did this, but maybe it’s part of some fraternity initiation thing, like TP-ing the dean’s house on Halloween. Here’s the story. Hendry writes: ‘Prior distributions’ widely used in Bayesian analyses, whether subjective or ‘objective’, cannot be formed in such a setting either, absent a falsely assumed crys

4 0.85216057 1182 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-24-Untangling the Jeffreys-Lindley paradox

Introduction: Ryan Ickert writes: I was wondering if you’d seen this post , by a particle physicist with some degree of influence. Dr. Dorigo works at CERN and Fermilab. The penultimate paragraph is: From the above expression, the Frequentist researcher concludes that the tracker is indeed biased, and rejects the null hypothesis H0, since there is a less-than-2% probability (P’<α) that a result as the one observed could arise by chance! A Frequentist thus draws, strongly, the opposite conclusion than a Bayesian from the same set of data. How to solve the riddle? He goes on to not solve the riddle. Perhaps you can? Surely with the large sample size they have (n=10^6), the precision on the frequentist p-value is pretty good, is it not? My reply: The first comment on the site (by Anonymous [who, just to be clear, is not me; I have no idea who wrote that comment], 22 Feb 2012, 21:27pm) pretty much nails it: In setting up the Bayesian model, Dorigo assumed a silly distribution on th

5 0.84843737 342 andrew gelman stats-2010-10-14-Trying to be precise about vagueness

Introduction: I recently saw this article that Stephen Senn wrote a couple of years ago, criticizing Bayesian sensitivity analyses that relied on vague prior distributions. I’m moving more and more toward the idea that Bayesian analysis should include actual prior information, so I generally agree with his points. As I used to say when teaching Bayesian data analysis, a Bayesian model is modular, and different pieces can be swapped in and out as needed. So you might start with an extremely weak prior distribution, but if it makes a difference it’s time to bite the bullet and include more information. My only disagreement with Senn’s paper is in its recommendation to try the so-called fixed-effects analysis. Beyond the difficulties with terminology (the expressions “fixed” and “random” effects are defined in different ways by different people in the literature; see here for a rant on the topic which made its way into some of my articles and books), there is the problem that, when a model ge

6 0.83886588 2027 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-17-Christian Robert on the Jeffreys-Lindley paradox; more generally, it’s good news when philosophical arguments can be transformed into technical modeling issues

7 0.83094645 1941 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-16-Priors

8 0.82991737 1208 andrew gelman stats-2012-03-11-Gelman on Hennig on Gelman on Bayes

9 0.82757682 2109 andrew gelman stats-2013-11-21-Hidden dangers of noninformative priors

10 0.82670182 1946 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-19-Prior distributions on derived quantities rather than on parameters themselves

11 0.82426918 1529 andrew gelman stats-2012-10-11-Bayesian brains?

12 0.81975538 1779 andrew gelman stats-2013-03-27-“Two Dogmas of Strong Objective Bayesianism”

13 0.81633121 2129 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-10-Cross-validation and Bayesian estimation of tuning parameters

14 0.81130445 1955 andrew gelman stats-2013-07-25-Bayes-respecting experimental design and other things

15 0.80660152 1087 andrew gelman stats-2011-12-27-“Keeping things unridiculous”: Berger, O’Hagan, and me on weakly informative priors

16 0.80144244 2099 andrew gelman stats-2013-11-13-“What are some situations in which the classical approach (or a naive implementation of it, based on cookbook recipes) gives worse results than a Bayesian approach, results that actually impeded the science?”

17 0.79451311 1151 andrew gelman stats-2012-02-03-Philosophy of Bayesian statistics: my reactions to Senn

18 0.79315102 2305 andrew gelman stats-2014-04-25-Revised statistical standards for evidence (comments to Val Johnson’s comments on our comments on Val’s comments on p-values)

19 0.78330642 1572 andrew gelman stats-2012-11-10-I don’t like this cartoon

20 0.77714616 804 andrew gelman stats-2011-07-15-Static sensitivity analysis


similar blogs computed by lda model

lda for this blog:

topicId topicWeight

[(15, 0.022), (16, 0.103), (21, 0.024), (24, 0.234), (63, 0.013), (65, 0.012), (72, 0.044), (86, 0.068), (89, 0.011), (99, 0.318)]

similar blogs list:

simIndex simValue blogId blogTitle

1 0.98720551 2208 andrew gelman stats-2014-02-12-How to think about “identifiability” in Bayesian inference?

Introduction: We had some questions on the Stan list regarding identification. The topic arose because people were fitting models with improper posterior distributions, the kind of model where there’s a ridge in the likelihood and the parameters are not otherwise constrained. I tried to help by writing something on Bayesian identifiability for the Stan list. Then Ben Goodrich came along and cleaned up what I wrote. I think this might be of interest to many of you so I’ll repeat the discussion here. Here’s what I wrote: Identification is actually a tricky concept and is not so clearly defined. In the broadest sense, a Bayesian model is identified if the posterior distribution is proper. Then one can do Bayesian inference and that’s that. No need to require a finite variance or even a finite mean, all that’s needed is a finite integral of the probability distribution. That said, there are some reasons why a stronger definition can be useful: 1. Weak identification. Suppose that, wit

2 0.98360139 1367 andrew gelman stats-2012-06-05-Question 26 of my final exam for Design and Analysis of Sample Surveys

Introduction: 26. You have just graded an an exam with 28 questions and 15 students. You fit a logistic item- response model estimating ability, difficulty, and discrimination parameters. Which of the following statements are basically true? (Indicate all that apply.) (a) If a question is answered correctly by students with very low and very high ability, but is missed by students in the middle, it will have a high value for its discrimination parameter. (b) It is not possible to fit an item-response model when you have more questions than students. In order to fit the model, you either need to reduce the number of questions (for example, by discarding some questions or by putting together some questions into a combined score) or increase the number of students in the dataset. (c) To keep the model identified, you can set one of the difficulty parameters or one of the ability parameters to zero and set one of the discrimination parameters to 1. (d) If two students answer the same number of q

3 0.98238349 2201 andrew gelman stats-2014-02-06-Bootstrap averaging: Examples where it works and where it doesn’t work

Introduction: Aki and I write : The very generality of the boostrap creates both opportunity and peril, allowing researchers to solve otherwise intractable problems but also sometimes leading to an answer with an inappropriately high level of certainty. We demonstrate with two examples from our own research: one problem where bootstrap smoothing was effective and led us to an improved method, and another case where bootstrap smoothing would not solve the underlying problem. Our point in these examples is not to disparage bootstrapping but rather to gain insight into where it will be more or less effective as a smoothing tool. An example where bootstrap smoothing works well Bayesian posterior distributions are commonly summarized using Monte Carlo simulations, and inferences for scalar parameters or quantities of interest can be summarized using 50% or 95% intervals. A interval for a continuous quantity is typically constructed either as a central probability interval (with probabili

4 0.98146009 1240 andrew gelman stats-2012-04-02-Blogads update

Introduction: A few months ago I reported on someone who wanted to insert text links into the blog. I asked her how much they would pay and got no answer. Yesterday, though, I received this reply: Hello Andrew, I am sorry for the delay in getting back to you. I’d like to make a proposal for your site. Please refer below. We would like to place a simple text link ad on page http://andrewgelman.com/2011/07/super_sam_fuld/ to link to *** with the key phrase ***. We will incorporate the key phrase into a sentence so it would read well. Rest assured it won’t sound obnoxious or advertorial. We will then process the final text link code as soon as you agree to our proposal. We can offer you $200 for this with the assumption that you will keep the link “live” on that page for 12 months or longer if you prefer. Please get back to us with a quick reply on your thoughts on this and include your Paypal ID for payment process. Hoping for a positive response from you. I wrote back: Hi,

5 0.98145223 1474 andrew gelman stats-2012-08-29-More on scaled-inverse Wishart and prior independence

Introduction: I’ve had a couple of email conversations in the past couple days on dependence in multivariate prior distributions. Modeling the degrees of freedom and scale parameters in the t distribution First, in our Stan group we’ve been discussing the choice of priors for the degrees-of-freedom parameter in the t distribution. I wrote that also there’s the question of parameterization. It does not necessarily make sense to have independent priors on the df and scale parameters. In some sense, the meaning of the scale parameter changes with the df. Prior dependence between correlation and scale parameters in the scaled inverse-Wishart model The second case of parameterization in prior distribution arose from an email I received from Chris Chatham pointing me to this exploration by Matt Simpson of the scaled inverse-Wishart prior distribution for hierarchical covariance matrices. Simpson writes: A popular prior for Σ is the inverse-Wishart distribution [ not the same as the

6 0.9810046 1206 andrew gelman stats-2012-03-10-95% intervals that I don’t believe, because they’re from a flat prior I don’t believe

7 0.97970843 899 andrew gelman stats-2011-09-10-The statistical significance filter

8 0.97876889 351 andrew gelman stats-2010-10-18-“I was finding the test so irritating and boring that I just started to click through as fast as I could”

9 0.97873402 494 andrew gelman stats-2010-12-31-Type S error rates for classical and Bayesian single and multiple comparison procedures

10 0.97869337 1713 andrew gelman stats-2013-02-08-P-values and statistical practice

11 0.97822583 1019 andrew gelman stats-2011-11-19-Validation of Software for Bayesian Models Using Posterior Quantiles

12 0.97804928 2055 andrew gelman stats-2013-10-08-A Bayesian approach for peer-review panels? and a speculation about Bruno Frey

13 0.97747833 1881 andrew gelman stats-2013-06-03-Boot

14 0.97747552 2086 andrew gelman stats-2013-11-03-How best to compare effects measured in two different time periods?

15 0.97725403 846 andrew gelman stats-2011-08-09-Default priors update?

same-blog 16 0.97724032 1695 andrew gelman stats-2013-01-28-Economists argue about Bayes

17 0.97722208 2040 andrew gelman stats-2013-09-26-Difficulties in making inferences about scientific truth from distributions of published p-values

18 0.97683954 1644 andrew gelman stats-2012-12-30-Fixed effects, followed by Bayes shrinkage?

19 0.97682297 2149 andrew gelman stats-2013-12-26-Statistical evidence for revised standards

20 0.97625506 2299 andrew gelman stats-2014-04-21-Stan Model of the Week: Hierarchical Modeling of Supernovas